RIGHTS TALK: THE IMPOVERISHMENT OF POLITICAL DISCOURSE
By Mary Ann Glendon
The Free Press
CHAPTER ONE – THE
In Tocqueville’s ten-month study of
At
least until the 1950s the principle focus of constitutional law was not
personal liberty, but the division of authority between the states and the
federal government.
Pg. 5. Today
the bulk of the Court’s constitutional work involves the claims that individual
rights have been violated. The shift
was, of course, with the civil rights generation. Law got more attractive and exciting as a
major. This change has obscured the
important roles that federalism, legislation and the separation of powers still
can and must play in safeguarding rights and freedom.
This
was born of spotting racism and corruption in local politics that made normal
activist channels difficult. Brown v.
Board also inspired. Legal tactics were
preferred to voter’s rights gain and the hard work of organizing in the
political arena where one might only be able to gain a compromise. The courts started to interfere in the
running of prisons, hospitals and school systems in every locale.
Our
vocabulary change is as dramatic as the legal.
Pg. 9. We say we can do whatever we please, but
when we think of criminal law we know that is not true. But the American version of the language of
rights is the language of no compromises whatsoever. In the Republic absolute freedom is said to
be great until the details are unpacked (no one has to go to war or participate
in government).
The words of the Declaration of
Independence and World War II provide the basis of American version of rights. P. 12. What is unique in our version is the way that
American rights talk (separate from the way we live and talk in our
neighborhoods and families) is that right are presented as being individual,
absolute and free from implying responsibilities. This characteristic is clear when you look at
the way rights are discussed in other liberal democracies. When
Our language comes from a melding of the
Anglo-American rights tradition with the more nuanced dialect of rights and
responsibility associated with the Romano-Germanic legal traditions. These are further blended with the
Enlightenment declarations. We do Hobbes
and Locke without the continental Rousseau and Kant. Another peculiar bent is our total substantiation
of the individual.
We expand rights without an eye to the
end in mind. Our limited vocabulary
makes us like a foreigner who can say “food” “Shelter” and that’s it. Limited conversation. It walls us off from our fellow
citizens. She does not wish to get rid
of rights, but deepen our talk about them so they reflect our common
understanding of lived reality. We need
to balance the rights vision of the Founders with the republic talk. But how can this be nourished?
CHAPTER TWO – THE ILLUSION OF ABSOLUTENESS
p.
18 A man’s home was his castle, but apartments bring
us into an “auditory intimacy” with our neighbors. One person’s children’s noise can breach the
moat of distance. The judge told them to
work it out civilly. No right to
eviction, no right to make as much noise as you wish.
English
law has legislative, not judicial, supremacy.
Not being shared by
p.
21 The origin of our version goes back to Locke the
story teller in his Second Treatise of Government where he tells of the “state
of nature” and “all the World was
Rousseau, by contrast, said man in nature
had no property. Locke’s treatise was
meant to bolster limitations on royalty.
Once parliamentary prerogatives were established, it was dropped in
All the founders were steeped in
Blackstone. P. 24 The
founders had seen how State governments had trammeled property rights in the
name of democracy and so saw it as being of central importance. It provided a convenient symbol for the ways
in which government must be limited. It
symbolized responsibility for self.
This
created problems from the beginning.
The 5th amendment specifically recognized eminent
domain. In the
But
they overwhelmingly sided with property.
The Dreadful Dred Scott case went the other way. And they continued to invalidate public
safety measures on the basis of property rights. The State Courts said a man’s home was inviolable. Public rights were a product of the 1930s
court and 1937 National Labor Relations Act where they upheld the right of the
government to have minimum wage laws. In
the 1950s they really allowed any eminent domain a legislature conjured
up. Pg. 30 Poletown in
In
the 1960s welfare and jobs began to be reconceptualized as form of property for
constitutional purposes. The right has tried
to get property rights back to being absolute, but they are a shell of their
former self.
Rousseau
said private property was a crime.
Greeks worried about private orientation and greed and the Bible speaks
of stewardship and your duty to the community.
It is arguable that Rousseau’s greatest contribution to Western
scholarship was to keep these two sources alive in our minds. P. 34, keeping us in touch
with
The
post Napoleon re-established French monarch made no attempt to give the
property back to those the revolution had stolen it from. This reality informed the whole
continent.
The
US Supreme Court, “began in the 1950s to expand the
constitutional protection of a broad range of personal rights-freedom of
expression, equal protection of the laws, and various rights of criminal
defendants. Meanwhile, all
Pre-political
rights looked appealing. There has been
a problem finding grounding for these rights however. And few of these rights are presented as
absolutes. The Canadian Charter of
Rights and Freedoms of 1982 guarantees rights, “subject only to subject only to
reasonable limits prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified in a free
and democratic society.” The German
Basic Law of 1949 says that property imposes duties to serve the public
weal.
Dworkin is very Blackstone.
Many of the individual rights now exerted borrow in language from that
developed for property in the
P. 42. The stark language of the 1st Amendment
gives the appearance of absolutes and Justice Black said he believed in “Absolutes.” The deference and place given freedom of
speech is a sign of the essential dependence of our democratic political order
upon ongoing reasoned deliberation. Respect
for that process of deliberation would seem to require truth-telling about
rights. Many who want a strict
interpretation of the second want a loose interpretation of the first.
But
this stark language cannot explain our embracing of absolutes where others won’t. Property isn’t even an unqualified right in
our constitution (the fifth). The roots
of our take on rights must be found elsewhere (Locke and Blackstone). P. 44. But on top of
this the pervasive legal nature of our consciousness is a cause. We are the most lawyer ridden society on
earth and that whose lawyers are the most adversarial.
Claims
of absoluteness have the ill effect that they downgrade rights into the mere
expression of desires and wants. They
express our most infantile nature. Rights
talk silences responsibility talk.
Seatbelt laws for example. Helmetless riders have loved ones and become helpless and
expensive in the hospital.
CHAPTER THREE – THE LONE RIGHTS-BEARER
Karl Marx was the first to
note that life liberty and property are the rights of a separated, independent
individual. The Court did not make the
right to privacy from whole cloth. It is
implicit in Locke, Hobbes and Blackstone.
Where did this individual self-sufficient image come from?
Again,
John Locke said we had property in nature, but we entered into government to
protect our property more efficiently.
Blackstone always said this “absolute” right was a residuum of natural
liberty.
Mill saw privacy of the private life, not
based on right, but fear of government.
p. 49. The
major spur to legal rights to privacy came from photography and mass
communication. The rich were the first
to feel their personal lives being made private.
Brandeis laid the theoretical grounding
for the right to privacy in a Harvard Law Review article. It was grounded in the right to enjoy your
property. P. 53 He coupled this with
Mill’s fear that the mediocre masses will stifle the lone genius’ potential
(though they didn’t cite him?). Brandeis
later said that publicity could clean folks up.
Brandeis dissented in a wire tap case and said the fourth and fifth gave
a right to privacy. The right to be let
alone was called, by the 1950s, the underlying principle of the Bill of
Rights. But the right to privacy did not
flower until 1965’s Griswold v.
In 1972 it became the right of individuals to
be protected in Eisenstadt v Baird and then Roe v.
Wade in 1973. The fetus was not a person
and so they had no contravening rights.
Laws requiring she be given information or the option of help for adoption
were considered to interfere with her isolation. There was no grounding for this right. It was absolute.
In 1986
the court narrowly upheld a
P. 61. Other countries
have gone different ways. The French, in
1881, said you had a right not to have your picture published without your
consent. German Basic Law of 1949 says “Everyone
shall have the right to the free development of his personality in so far as he
does not violate the rights of others or offend against the constitutional order or the moral code.” The word used for development means folding
out.
p. 64. German statues
further specify that you may not violate another’s right. They had a nearly identical case to Roe v.
Wade. They answered it in the light of
their “confrontation” with National Socialism.
This implied that they had to protect life. They also considered the ethical message sent
by a law allowing abortion on demand!
Thus it went back to the legislature who put information and waiting
periods and steps in the way to allow it, but with the appropriate moral
gravity and difficulty accompanying it. They
are also entitled to lots of single mom support and help if they will take it
to term. All our women get, by contrast,
is a right to privacy. We cannot even
give information because it implies the state making a moral wedge and
statement. In our system it is only a
decontextualized war of rights. Right to choose, right to life.
p. 67. We are much
more likely to be able to print anything about anyone. In
But this is backed up by a deeper understanding
of the individual. Locke, Hobbes and
Rousseau’s myths about the individual in nature saw him as unmolested or
seeking to be. Rousseau alone saw alone
as healthy and natural. His great
admirer, Kant, also saw man as a solitary thinker. And Adam Smith turned us into homo economicus (selfish, calculating and seeking
self-sufficiency).
None wrote of the family nor
of women. They wrote of “man”. Locke, to disprove the analogy of monarch to
citizen as father to child, put bad spins of the family that included Incans
eating their children. Rousseau, more
accepted on the continent, did say that socialization was needed for the
individual and so, like Plato, stressed education.
Marx noted that none of the rights of man go
beyond the egoistic man.
p. 71 The West German Constitutional Court in
1970 said that the “The concept of man in the Basic Law is not that of an
isolated, sovereign individual; rather, the Basic Law resolves the conflict
between the individual and the community
by relating and binding the citizen to the community, but without detracting
from his individuality.” It is a departure from classical individualism and
rejects collectivism.
Kant influenced Wilhelm Von Humboldt who
influenced Mill.
Our decontextualized man runs into most trouble
when making laws for procreation, family relations or child rearing. Our divorce laws assume individual
self-sufficiency as do our aid to dependent family laws.
The French 1946 Constitution says that “The
nation shall unsure to the individual and the family the conditions necessary
to their development.” The German
Basic Law also protects “Marriage and family”.
Duty to children Protection of mothers. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights
also recognizes the family.
p. 74 Parents are ill served by laws that treat
their families as “life-styles.” The
elderly and frail also need more help than rights to autonomy. Our lack of vocabulary about things other
than the individual creates the situation it is limited to speaking about.
CHAPTER FOUR – THE MISSING LANGUAGE OF RESPONSIBILITY
We nor government have no duty to help others.
We have a right to ignore those in mortal danger. European constitutions do impose this duty on
individuals and governments. The Yania case establishes our right not to help others who are
in trouble. In 1980 it was held that an
Aunt had no duty to warn her 11 year old nephew that the seat on the power
mower was loose.
P. 80 Lawyers are socialized
by discussing these cases in their first year.
An Olympic swimmer has no duty to rescue a drowning baby. They are challenged to find a basis upon
which this duty my hang. The message is
that the law distinguishes between acts and omissions. And another is that they should not make the
mistake of confusing their personal notions of morality and the law.
The right to negligence is
especially true if the folks involved have not entered into a “special relation”
where there is an expectation of protection.
Nephews and neighbors are, legally, strangers. In no legal codes are there duties to help
others. Social norms were the source of
this duty. The law now seems to condone
anti-social behaviors and only considers changing to the tune of requiring
damages be paid, not duty required.
Pg. 84 In France, the
person is liable to the public and public prosecution, but not liable to the
people involved. Why do we only look at tort (damages)
laws? Perhaps it represents our
traditional preference for private, rather than public, solutions. But another factor is that in Romano-Germanic
systems of Continental law criminal codes reflect reinforcing widely shared
minimal standards of behavior. The
rescue laws remind us that we a part of society and have duties to good
citizenship. We are uncomfortable with
law touching moral sense. We have
stressed the separation of law and morals for much of the twentieth
century.
It is a nation of laws, not men. She is not suggesting that law should go back
to being the moral schoolteacher it was in colonial times. A nineteenth-century English jurist wrote “Law
cannot be better than the nation in which it exists, though it may and can
protect an acknowledged moral standard, and may gradually be increased in
strictness as the standard rises.”
We see law as command, as
in Hobbes, and so resist it. Others law
as agreement ala Kant and Rousseau, who accept it.
P. 86.
Holmes in the most widely quoted legal article ever written by an American
roundly denounced the “confusion between legal and moral ideas.” He expounded a strong moral relativism, where
my morals and the others were just personal desires. Researchers found that if a law were passed
about the duty to rescue, people would view those who didn’t comply more
harshly because they thought the law stemmed from representing the majority
opinion. Some states have enacted “good Samaritan”
laws that give people immunity from damage if they were trying to help.
p. 89 Do police have the
duty to help?
In DeShaney v.
Winnebago the Supreme Court asked if the State could be sued for failing to
remove a boy being beaten by a father on behalf of the absentee mother. There was no special relation between the
child and the department of social services.
It is not a violation, said Rehnquist, of the due process clause. He was not deprived by the state. The abuse did not happen in a state foster
home.
P. 94 Justice Brennan dissented. He said the county did not competently follow
through on a duty it had voluntarily taken upon itself. Rehnquist said no, you have no right to
government aid. This could be
interpreted to say that we are a nation of strangers. Rehnquist said we are in the “free world”, this unfortunate choice of words would not sound good to
the boy who was beaten. Court opinions
are, however, not addressed to the litigants, but to the community of
interpreters. A nicer opinion would have mentioned the remedies that were
available to the boy and family ($50,000 from
She worries that this decision has sent an
alienating message to the general public.
The message is also sent out to public officials. She also admits, however, that if they had
been allowed huge sums of money, it might not have secured better services in
P. 98 How do other countries conceive of the
obligation to come to the aid of the needy?
We have no constitutional commitment to it. In most Western European states, the
constitution guarantees old-age pensions, national health care and unemployment
compensation on par with free speech and rights of property. Rehnquist’s statement would not fly
there. When they did their post WW II
constitutions they added positive rights.
This European language does not necessarily
mean, however, that the rights are enforceable.
These pare called “programmatic rights,” or statements of public goals
and social aspirations whose implementation must await legislative or executive
action and budgetary appropriations. And
we do have comparable rights under the welfare state established in the
1930s. These cannot be withdrawn without
due process of law. Nor can they be
distributed unequally.
These programs keep responsibilities of the
citizen and state prominently in view along with rights.
P. 101 There is a traditional silence in
American law, however, regarding the duties of the citizens individually or collectively
to come to the aid of one another. When
the constitution was written government was to be small. Now it has usurped all and the customary
norms have diminished. Law goes where no
other institutions go. Americans today,
rightly or wrongly, regard many legal norms, especially those of criminal,
family, and constitutional law, as expressions of minimal common values. So we need to be very careful when we defend
restatements of older positions.
No duty to rescue sits uneasy with us because
there are so many places with no community. As social bonds become weaker a moral vacuum
arises. Law tends to move into this
vacuum. We have not generated a language
about responsibility. Blackstone guards property, DOI says our rights are inalienable but
only mention the duty to overthrow bad governments. The general welfare did not mean a welfare
state and when the 1930s one came it was not delivering a hibernating promise,
but against our background of government distrust.
p. 105 Legislators need to be aware of the
pedagogical dimensions of the laws they pass.
These laws say what kind of people we are and what kind of society we
are creating.
p. 106 All over the Western world, divorce
became easy on no-fault grounds in the 1970s and 1980s. There are three approaches to the problems of
continued dependency after divorce. The
continental pattern in
We would not endorse the notion that we can
divorce our children, but the law does and the state shows indifference.
CHAPTER FIVE – THE MISSING DIMENSION OF SOCIALITY
p. 110 The
flag burning dispute puts rights talk against a vacuum of vocabulary concerning
community. There is a disagreement
between those who equate all widely held standards with oppression and those
who regard the extension of constitutional protection to flag burning, child pornography,
or sadomasochistic art and all the practices and procedures through which a
society constantly defines and redefines itself.
A 60 day notice
requirement in
The Sierra club could not
sue to preserve federal parkland as a shared natural resource. They had to find individuals that were
harmed. Except with corporations, which
have been defined as individuals, the law does not recognize groups or
associations well.
P. 115 Associations are
seen as interest groups: groups of self-serving individuals. There hasn’t been that big a need to take
care of such things. At the Founding,
these familial and community associations just seemed natural. That is not to say that they did not think
these social institutions were important.
Jefferson, Adams and especially Madison stressed their importance.
They could not have for seen
the bureaucratic dependence of the populace, the flourishing and deterioration
of public education. They assumed the social
environment would always just be there.
P.
117 The French revolutionaries sought to get rid of
institutions that competed for loyalty with the state. They sought to make the people, society, and
the state one. Napoleon stopped attacks
on institutions and brought the social society under the wing the central
government. Tocqueville, Durkheim,
Hegel, Marx and Burke about what might happen if social institutions became
weaker as government became stronger. Tocqueville and Burke particularly saw a connection
between rootedness and civic virtue and the danger of selfish private
orientations. Tocqueville saw hope in
private associations and Durkheim called them “secondary groups.” The State is too remote to bring unity.
Whereas Marx thought the State
would wither away, it has in fact gotten stronger and society has withered
away. Our rights bearing vocabulary
doesn’t give us a way to bring it back.
Family values are talked
of often by politicians. These are
platitudes. Those involved are more
interested in yelling at each other than actual families. The right talks about “traditional” families
as a “basic social unit.” The left sees
the traditional family as “patriarchal” artificial and oppressive. They speak of “families” rather than the “family”. The right says laissez faire economics will
bring back the family reliance. The left
says no, redouble support efforts. Voters
are frustrated in having to choose between these two positions.
p. 122 Until the 1960s law
held the ideas on the cultural right.
Marriage was treated as an important support institution. Father had most decision making power. Family members could not enforce contracts
against each other or sue each other.
Women were to be faithful and children born out of wedlock had hardly
any legal standing at all.
Now the legal assumptions
look like those of the cultural left. Divorce
is an individual right that one spouse can enter into. Gender based distinctions are gone. Family members can sue each other. Formal and informal marriage distinctions
have been blurred and there are no legal discriminations against children born outside
of marriage. Child support has been
largely replaced with the idea that the spouses should be self-sufficient
outside of marriage - spousal support, if awarded, should be temporary. Families are treated as a collection of
individuals. The discussions over what a
family is reflect its final deconstruction.
The traditional family
does seem to exist when the ids are small and then go to a dual income model
after that. This is ignored by family
deconstructers. That gender differences
can be disregarded is an unrealistic as the notion that they can be rigidly
prescribed. Women are more financially
vulnerable in divorces. The wife does
most child care. Generally family has
been defined as a household with more than one generation. That is being challenged.
Our stake in children
being raised is greater than how adults choose to arrange their lives. Europeans differentiate between households
engaged in raising children and those who are not. We are coming at this definition
slowly.
P. 126 In
the 1970s a regulation about a neighborhood being for families excluding
grandmothers raising kids was struck down.
What of single moms or homosexual couples? All agree that healthy families are
important, but how to create them is very
disputed.
The disputants do not worry about the
continuation of a free, democratic, and egalitarian regime. But liberal democracies are not a given. SHE
HIT IT! Character is a part of
this. We shy away from such discussions
because we do not want to seem judgmental.
We do not consider the emotional and financial costs to the
children. The duties to uphold the
recreation of society take a distant back seat to individual rights and prerogatives.
When asked what makes a good citizen only seven
percent of young people mention our being a democracy. People for the
P. 130 We need to
switch from thinking about family policy to family ecology. Family policy is about setting up conditions
for the future. Urie
Bronfenbrenner has written about human ecology. A study in
This was done just as families started to
disintegrate and so highlight the importance of community connections. In 1960 fewer than 10 percent of American
children lived in a single-parent home.
By 1988 it was 25%. More than
half of all children born in the 1980s will spend part of their childhood in
single parent homes. Nearly half of all
female-headed families with children under six live in poverty.
The community supports are important but they
in turn depended on families. Law cannot
replace families or communities, but it can at least seek not to undermine the
social structures upon which they rely.
We should not treat child-raising as just another life-style
choice. Tax, zoning, and social
assistance laws should take credence of their affect. We should not apologize for defining our
society as one that relies heavily on families to socialize its young and
encourages, aids and rewards this endeavor.
We should refer to natural ecology
systems. But Michael Walzer
has warned that the four mobilities, Geographic,
Social , Political and Social has resulted in there being no out there to rally
but separated, rights-bearing, voluntarily associating, freely speaking,
liberal Americans. We are living on
inherited social capital, consuming our resources without replenishing
them.
P. 137 Group rights language doesn’t help. These pit groups against individuals, one
group against another, and group against state.
Oppression and tribalism lurk there.
Group rights are ephemeral, not communities. They can also be NIMBY. No prisons, foster homes, mentally retarded
or public works here. We need rather, a
more ecological way of thinking about social policy. Groups are important, but not for their own
sake.
When individual rights are able to undermine
communities they destroy their underpinnings.
Free markets, strong states and civil society are all potential threats
to individual citizens. But a weakness
in any puts the entire democratic enterprise in danger.
She likes the vouchers for private child care
centers idea. These strengthen private
community institutions. Old people can
work in these church based centers.
Adolescent pregnancy laws are another case in
point. The Adolescent Family Life Act
(ALFA) gives grants to private organizations to develop programs to assist
teenage parents and research into what causes it. It is community based legislation. Was it to allow funding for birth control or
abortions thought? But it saw government
being interested in social ecology. It
does not organize communities, but helps community groups already in
place. In an encouraging decision, the
Supreme Court upheld the challenge to ALFA on church/state grounds. P. 142 The decision showed a growing Court
willingness to appreciate civil society.
CHAPTER SIX -
RIGHTS INSULARITY
“But a great civilization
can also be recognized by its refusal to borrow, by its resistance to certain
alignments, by its resolute selection among the foreign influences offered to
it . . . “ Fernand Braudel
When asked to identify 16
places on a map we, of course, came in last.
We are also unconcerned with the legal culture of the rest of the
world. It is ironic that we have
contributed so much to the judicial world, but now barely participate in
it.
In both places
anti-homosexual laws were challenged.
Mr. Dudgeon did so in
Article 8 reads:
1. Everyone has the
right to respect for his private life and family life, is home and his correspondence.
2. There shall be
no interference by a public authority with the exercise of this right except
such as is in the interests of national security, public safety or the economic
well-being of the country, for the prevention of disorder or crime, for the
protection of health or morals, or for the protection of the rights and
freedoms of others.
Mr. Hardwick challenged in
There being a
supranational court is new. The Dudgeon
case of
Our
own Justice White said his right to privacy was not violated as there is no
right to sodomy. The other side said he
had the “right to be let alone” and that “a man’s home is his castle.” It wasn’t very
nuanced. Both White and Blackmun said that the right either had to be fundamental
or not at all. Neither looked into
whether or not there was a rational basis for the
White’s opinion gives
the feeling of callousness towards the feeling of a minority in the way that
the Euro court’s decision does not.
Their decision gives fewer grounds for gloating and alienation or
anger. Our talk jeopardizes the
legitimacy of the court.
When we do the rights talk
take, we end up with there being no grounds for distinction between homosexies and heterosexies or discrimination
based on nothing. The Euro decision did
not carry implications for employment, housing, adoption, family benefits the
way that rights talk does.
It is ironic that the
European judges have become pragmatic, principled and flexible when these were
once the pride of American common law. Cardozo and John Marshall Harlan would be unhappy.
Courts know about our
decisions and we do not know about theirs.
To some degree our reticence comes from prudent unwillingness to render
ourselves vulnerable to institutions heavily staffed by critics of
P. 160 Time magazine in a
bicentennial issue called our Constitution “a gift to all nations because some
160 of the then 170 countries had written charters modeled directly or
indirectly on ours. More than half of
all existing constitutions were adopted since the mid-1970s. They are overwhelmingly parliamentary. The feature that gets the most attention is
the enumeration of rights and the independent judiciary empowered to back them
up.
The values given
constitutional status since WW II have included social as well as individual
rights. The formulation
of these are more nuanced than our DOI or B of R. Many rights are viewed as inseparable from
responsibilities, liberty and equality are seen as coordinated and fraternity
gets its day in court too. Personal
values are regarded as higher than social ones, but also as being rooted in
them.
Most foreign judiciaries
have shied from allowing courts to rule on constitutional questions. Many use a tribunal for such issues. And these are more circumspect than our
courts.
Much of our judicial
activism is attributed to a historical time when confidence in our state
legislatures was low. We have really
moved personal liberties into the foreground.
We are studied here because we are seen to have a lot of experience with
this and judicial review. But, in
reality, judicial review was little used until recently. Where rights pertaining to fair criminal
procedure, equal legal treatment, free expression, or privacy are concerned,
the
P. 164 In 1982
The differences in
interpretation history were necessary due to the differences in culture.
The Canadian constitution
recognizes limits on rights, group rights, but not property rights.
P 168 In
Europe our influence is mitigated by knowledge of us being second hand through
scholars. And our interpreters tend to
be advocates for individual rights and insensitive to context in a way that
doesn’t make sense to others. Our case
study with 200 years behind it is also very complicated to digest.
Still our scholarship
helps other countries to think better about their own problems. It would be good if we availed ourselves of
their experience.
CHAPTER SEVEN – REFINING THE RHETORIC OF RIGHTS
P. 171 Our simple rights
talk contributes to the erosion of the habits, practices and attitudes of
respect for others that are the ultimate and surest guarantors of human
rights. It impedes our creative
long-range thinking. It accommodates the
economic, immediate and personal but neglects the moral, long-term and social
implications.
Rights talk is turning our
discourse into a parody of itself and killing the idea of compromise. This individual desire based egoism is in
direct contrast to the purposes set up in the preamble. Refining the discourse of rights will not
help our vacuous, hard-edged and inflexible discourse. We hope this talk is not a mirror of our
actual society. If not, what tools in
society can we use to rescue ourselves. Here she speaks of Bellah’s
“first language” of individualism. Self-expression
and self-glorification have replaced self-reliance and self-discipline. Lasch says we have
lost the patriotic, biblical and folkloric legends that once provided young
people with ideals towards which they might grow.
We still, however, tend to
live and work in communities and have table talk and family histories. Traditionally women have taken the lead in
transmitting family lore and educating children. Feminist vocabularies of caretaking are
important here. We should discourage
exaggeration absolutes and litigation.
Many judges take context and the understanding that neither side is 100%
right into account. Immigrant groups are
also a source of different thinking like the native Americans
who were hippie stewards of nature. The
biblical language of stewardship helps too.
This is better than a “right” to a healthy environment.
P. 176 The greatest hope
for renewal perhaps lies in the American political tradition itself. Properly understood liberalism has a moral
core and assumes community. We should
think of the social costs of rights and what effects a given right can be
expected to have on the setting. Our
very heterogeneity that makes us go for abstract sources of unity can help
us.
But would a dynamic leader
bring this message to us? New media
works against this idea. Those who are
most powerful are often those least tied into tangible community. Mill warned of the soft tyranny of the stupid
majority. The “labor beat” has
disappeared from American newspapers.
There is a growing gap between those who work in
We need not only public
discourse, but the conditions for public deliberation. Leaders must provide models of
discussion? Information,
forums, facts and places where interests and interests can be exchanged. We need political platforms that attract
folks and not the clashing of unyielding interests in irreconcilable
conflict. We need to respect each
other. We need civility.
The Supreme Court seems to
be loosening up the reigns on legislatures and local control. People are starting to rebel against the idea
that morals and religious talk don’t belong in public discourse.
Perhaps some can, like Dr.
King, help us to bridge our gaps and disagree without losing mutual respect. Our diversity and opportunities for
experimentation our society allows may prove fertile ground for renewal.